Consequentialism says that right or wrong depend on the consequences of an act, and that the more good consequences are produced, the better the act.
Consequentialism says that right or wrong depend on the consequences of an act, and that the more good consequences are produced, the better the act.
The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy gives a plain and simple definition of consequentialism:
Of all the things a person might do at any given moment, the morally right action is the one with the best overall consequences.
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Consequentialism
Consequentialism is based on two principles:
It gives us this guidance when faced with a moral dilemma:
And it gives this general guidance on how to live:
Different forms of consequentialism differ over what the good thing is that should be maximised.
In practice people don't assess the ethical consequences of every single act (that's called 'act consequentialism') because they don't have the time.
Instead they use ethical rules that are derived from considering the general consequences of particular types of acts. That is called 'rule consequentialism'.
Results-based ethics produces this important conclusion for ethical thinking:
This far-fetched example may make things clearer:
The classic form of results-based ethics is called utilitarianism.
This says that the ethically right choice in a given situation is the one that produces the most happiness and the least unhappiness for the largest number of people.
Results-based ethics plays a very large part in everyday life because it is simple and appeals to common sense:
Act consequentialism looks at every single moral choice anew. It teaches:
Rule consequentialism bases moral rules on their consequences. This removes many of the problems of act consequentialism.
Rule consequentialism teaches:
So when an individual has a moral choice to make they can ask themselves if there's an appropriate rule to apply and then apply it.
The rules that should be adopted are the rules that would produce the best results if they were adopted by most people.
Philosophers express this with greater precision:
And here's another version:
An action is morally right if and only if it does not violate the set of rules of behaviour whose general acceptance in the community would have the best consequences--that is, at least as good as any rival set of rules or no rules at all.
Internet Encyclopedia of Philisophy: Consequentialism
Negative consequentialism is the inverse of ordinary consequentialism. Good actions are the ones that produce the least harm.
Consequentialism has both practical and philosophical problems:
And these are things that many think are relevant to ethical judgements.
However, in support of consequentialism it might be argued that many of the things listed above do influence the good or bad consequences of an act, particularly when formulating ethical rules, and so they become incorporated in consequentialist ethical thinking; but only through the back door, not directly.
Simple forms of consequentialism say that the best action is the one that produces the largest total of happiness.
This ignores the way in which that happiness is shared out and so would seem to approve of acts that make most people happy, and a few people very unhappy, or that make a few people ecstatically happy and leave the majority at best neutral.
It also detracts from the value of individuals and their own interests and projects, other than when those are in line with the interests of the group.
Consider this situation:
A billionaire needs an organ transplant. He says that if he is given the next suitable organ he will fund 1000 hip-replacements a year for 10 years. Giving him the next available organ means Mr X, who was top of the list, will die - but it also means that thousands of people will be very happy with their new hips.
Consequentialism might be used to argue that Mr X's human rights (and his and his family's happiness) should be ignored, in order to increase the overall amount of human well-being.
´óÏó´«Ã½ © 2014 The ´óÏó´«Ã½ is not responsible for the content of external sites. Read more.
This page is best viewed in an up-to-date web browser with style sheets (CSS) enabled. While you will be able to view the content of this page in your current browser, you will not be able to get the full visual experience. Please consider upgrading your browser software or enabling style sheets (CSS) if you are able to do so.